Roger Fry Essay In Aesthetics

Posted on
  1. Roger Fry Essay In Aesthetics
  2. Roger Fry An Essay In Aesthetics
  3. Roger Fry An Essay In Aesthetics

Roger fry an essay in aesthetics summary. October 12, 2018 Roger fry an essay in aesthetics summary. Topic a college essay mental illness. Hobby and interest essay engineering; Essay writer app software; Essay on caring your school library; Write a descriptive essay about davy. The incredibles essay personal literacy narrative essays for a restaurant brevets 2016 sujets de dissertation astrophil and stella sonnet 20 analysis essay university of mississippi application essay riot and remembrance essay myth of global warming essays essay on raksha bandhan in punjabi vich research paper on basel ii accord luha ng buwaya.

<p>AN</p><p>ESSAY</p><p>IN</p><p>JESTHETICS</p><p>*</p><p>CERTAIN painter, not without some reputation at the present day, once wrote a little book on the art he practises, in which he gave a definition of that art so succinct that I take it as a point of departure for this essay. ' The art of painting,' ays that eminent authority, ' is the art of imitating solid objects upon a flat surface by means of pigments.' It is delightfully simple, but prompts the question-Is that all? And, if so, what a deal of unnecessary fuss has been made about it. Now, it is useless to deny that our modern writer has some very respectable authorities behind him. Plato, indeed, gave a very similar account of the affair, and himself put the question-is it then worth while? And, being scrupulously and relentlessly logical, he decided that it was not worth while, and proceeded to turn the artists out of his ideal republic. For all that, the world has continued obstinately to consider that painting was worth while, and though, indeed, it has never quite made up its mind as to what, exactly, the graphic arts did for it, it has persisted in honouring and admiring its painters. Can we arrive at any conclusions as to the nature of the graphic arts, which will at all explain our feelings about them, which will at least put them into some kind of relation with the other arts, and not leave us in the extreme perplexity, engendered by any theory of mere imitation? For, I suppose, it must be admitted that if imitation is the sole purpose of the graphic arts, it is surprising that the works of such arts are ever looked upon as more than curiosities, or ingenious toys, are ever taken seriously by grown-up people. Moreover, it will be surprising that they have no recognisable affinity with other arts, such as music or architecture, in which the imitation of actual objects is a negligible quantity. To form such conclusions is the aim I have put before myself in this essay. Even if the results are not decisive, the inquiry may lead us to a view of the graphic arts that will not be altogether unfruitful.</p><p>A</p><p>*</p><p>New Quarterly,</p><p>1909.</p><p>12</p><p>VISION AND DESIGN</p><p>I must begin with some elementary psychology, with a con sideration of the nature of instincts. A great many objects in the world, when presented to our senses, put in motion a complex nervous machinery, which ends in some instinctive appropriate action. We see a wild bull in a field ; quite without our conscious interference a nervous process goes on, which, unless we interfere forcibly, ends in the appropriate reaction of flight. The nervous mechanism which results in flight causes a certain state of consciousness, which we call the emotion of fear. The whole of animal life, and a great part of human life, is made up of these instinctive reactions to sensible objects, and their accompanying emotions. But man has the peculiar faculty of calling up again in his mind the echo of past experience_s_of this kind, of going over it again, ' in imagination ' as we say. He has, ' therefore, the possibility of a double life ; one the actual life, the other the imaginative life. Between these two lives there is this great distinction, that in the actual life the processes of natural selection have brought it about that the instinctive reaction, such, for instance, as . flight from danger, shall be the important part of the whole process, and it is towards this that the man bends his whole conscious en deavour. But in the imaginative life no such action is necessary, and, therefore, the whole consciousness may be focussed upon the perceptive and the emotional aspects of the experience. In this way we get, in the imaginative life, a different set of values, and a different_ kind of perception. We can get a curious side glimpse of the nature of this imaginative life from the cinematograph. This resembles actual life in almost every respect, except that what the psychologists call the conative part of our reaction to sensations, that is to say, the appropriate resultant action is cut off. If, in a cinematograph, we see a runaway horse and cart, we do not have to think either of getting out of the way or heroically interposing ourselves. The result is that in the first place we see the event much more clearly ; see a number of quite interesting but irrelevant things, which in real life could not struggle into our consciousness, bent, as it would be, entirely upon the problem of our appropriate reaction. I remember seeing in a cine matograph the arrival of a train at a foreign station and the people descending from the carriages ; there was no platform, and to my</p><p>12</p><p>VISION AND DESIGN</p><p>I must begin with some elementary psychology, with a con sideration of the nature of instincts. A great many objects in the world, when presented to our senses, put in motion a complex nervous machinery, which ends in some instinctive appropriate action. We see a wild bull in a field ; quite without our conscious interference a nervous process goes on, which, unless we interfere forcibly, ends in the appropriate reaction of flight. The nervous mechanism which results in flight causes a certain state of consciousness, which we call the emotion of fear. The whole of animal life, and a great part of human life, is made up of these instinctive reactions to sensible objects, and their accompanying emotions. But man has the peculiar faculty of calling up again in his mind the echo of past experience_s_of this kind, of going over it again, ' in imagination ' as we say. He has, ' therefore, the possibility of a double life ; one the actual life, the other the imaginative life. Between these two lives there is this great distinction, that in the actual life the processes of natural selection have brought it about that the instinctive reaction, such, for instance, as . flight from danger, shall be the important part of the whole process, and it is towards this that the man bends his whole conscious en deavour. But in the imaginative life no such action is necessary, and, therefore, the whole consciousness may be focussed upon the perceptive and the emotional aspects of the experience. In this way we get, in the imaginative life, a different set of values, and a different_ kind of perception. We can get a curious side glimpse of the nature of this imaginative life from the cinematograph. This resembles actual life in almost every respect, except that what the psychologists call the conative part of our reaction to sensations, that is to say, the appropriate resultant action is cut off. If, in a cinematograph, we see a runaway horse and cart, we do not have to think either of getting out of the way or heroically interposing ourselves. The result is that in the first place we see the event much more clearly ; see a number of quite interesting but irrelevant things, which in real life could not struggle into our consciousness, bent, as it would be, entirely upon the problem of our appropriate reaction. I remember seeing in a cine matograph the arrival of a train at a foreign station and the people descending from the carriages ; there was no platform, and to my</p><p>AN ESSAY IN ltSTHETICS</p><p>I3</p><p>intense surprise I saw several people turn right round after reaching the ground, as though to orientate themselves; an almost ridiculous performance, which I had never noticed in all the many hundred occasions on which such a scene had passed before my eyes in real life. The fact being that at a station one is never really a spectator of events, but an actor engaged in the drama of luggage or prospective seats, and one actually sees only so much as may help to the appropriate action. In the second place, with regard to the visions of the cinemato graph, one notices that whatever emotions are aroused by them, though they arc likely to be weaker than those of ordinary life, are If the scene pre presented more clearly to the consciousness. sented be one of an accident, our pity and horror, though weak, since we know that no one is really hurt, are felt quite purely, since they cannot, as they would in life, pass at once into actions of assistance. A somewhat similar effect to that of the cinematograph can be obtained by watching a mirror in which a street scene is reflected. If we look at the street itself we are almost sure to adjust ourselves in some way to its actual existence. We recognise an acquaintance, and wonder why he looks so dejected this morning, or become interested in a new fashion in hats-the moment we do that the spell is broken, we are reacting to life itself in however slight a degree, but, in the mirror, it is easier to abstract ourselves completely, and look upon the changing scene as a whole. It then, at once, takes on the visionary quality, and we become true spectators, not selecting what we will see, but seeing everything equally, and thereby we come to notice a number of appearances and relations of appearances, which would have escaped our vision before, owing to that perpetual econo mising by selection of what impressions we will assimilate, which in life we perform by unconscious processes. The frame of the mirror then, does, to some extent, turn the reflected scene from one that belongs to our actual life into one that belongs rather to the imagina tive life. The frame of the mirror makes its surface into a very rudimentary work of art, since it helps us to attain to the artistic vision. For that is what, as you will already have guessed, I have been coming to all this time, namely that the work of art is intimately connected</p><p>14</p><p>VISION AND DESIGN</p><p>with the secondary imaginative life, which all men live to a greater or lesser extent. That the graphic arts are the expression of the imaginative life rather than a copy of actual life might be guessed from observing children. Children, if left to themselves, never, I believe, copy what they see, never, as we say, ' draw from nature,' but express, with a delightful freedom and sincerity, the mental images which make up their own imaginative lives. Art, then, is an expression and a stimulus of this imaginative life, which is separated from actual life by the absence of responsive action. Now this responsive action implies in actual life moral responsibility. fin art we have no such moral responsibility-it presents a life freed from the binding necessities of our actual existence: X'hat then is the justification for this life of the imagination -which all human beings live more or less fully? To the pure moralist, who accepts nothing but ethical values, in order to be justified, it must be shown not only not to hinder but actually to forward right action, otherwise it is not only useless but, since it absorbs our energies, positively harmful. To such a one two views are possible, one the Puritanical view at its narrowest, which regards the life of the imagina tion as no better or worse than a life of sensual pleasure, and therefore entirely reprehensible. The other view is to argue that the imagina tive life does subserve morality. And this is inevitably the view taken by moralists like Ruskin, to whom the imaginative life is yet an absolute necessity. It is a view which leads to some very hard special pleading, even to a self-deception which is in itself morally undesirable. But here comes in the question of religion, for religion is also an affair of the imaginative life, and, though it claims to have a direct effect upon conduct, I do not suppose that the religious person if he were wise would justify religion entirely by its effect on morality, . since that, historically speaking, has not been by any means uniformly advantageous. He would probably say that the religious experience was one which corresponded to certain spiritual capacities of human nature, the exercise of which is in itself good and desirable apart from their effect upon actual life. And so, too, I think the artist might if he chose take a mystical attitude, and declare that the fullness and completeness of the imaginative life he leads may correspond to</p><p>AN ESSAY IN lESTHETICS</p><p>15</p><p>an existence more real and more important than any that we know of in mortal life. And in saying that, his appeal would find a sympathetic echo In most minds, for most people would, I think, say that the pleasures derived from art were of an altogether different character and more fundamental than merely sensual pleasures, that they did exercise some faculties which are felt to belong to whatever part of us there may be which is not entirely ephemeral and material. It might even be that from this point of view we should rather justify actual life by its relation to the imaginative, justify nature by its likeness to art. I mean this, that since the imaginative life comes in the course of time to represent more or less what mankind feels to be the completest expression of its own nature, the freest use of its innate capacities, the actual life may be explained and justified in its approximation here and there, however partially and inadequately, to that freer and fuller life. Before leaving this question of the justification of art, let me put it in another way. The imaginative life of a people has very different levels at different times, and these levels do not always correspond with the general level of the morality of actual life. Thus in the thirteenth century we read of barbarity and cruelty which would shock even us ; we may I think admit that our moral level, our general humanity is decidedly higher to-day, but the level of our imaginative life is incomparably lower ; we are satisfied there with a grossness, a sheer barbarity and squalor which would have shocked the thirteenth century profoundly. Let us admit the moral gain gladly, but do we not also feel a loss ; do we not feel that the average business man would be in every way a more admirable, more respectable being if his imaginative life were not so squalid and incoherent? And, if we admit any loss then, there is some function in human nature other than a purely ethical one, which is worthy of exercise. Now the imaginative life has its own history both in the race and in the individual. In the individual life one of the first effects of freeing experience from the necessities of appropriate responsive action is to indulge recklessly the emotion of self-aggrandisement. The day-dreams of a child are filled with extravagant romances in which he is always the invincible hero. Music-which of all the arts</p><p>I6</p><p>VISION AND DESIGN</p><p>supplies the strongest stimulus to the imaginative life, and at the same time has the least power of controlling its direction-music, at certain stages of people's lives, has the effect merely of arousing in an almost absurd degree this egoistic elation, and Tolstoy appears to believe that this is its only possible effect. But with the teaching of experience and the growth of character the imaginative life comes to respond to other..</p>
1928 self-portrait
Born14 December 1866
Died9 September 1934 (aged 67)
Royal Free Hospital, Hampstead, London, England
NationalityBritish
EducationClifton College
Alma materKing’s College, Cambridge
OccupationArtist and art critic
Known forMember of the Bloomsbury Group

Roger fry an essay in aesthetics - wbsportsnews.com.

Roger Eliot Fry (14 December 1866 – 9 September 1934) was an English painter and critic, and a member of the Bloomsbury Group. Establishing his reputation as a scholar of the Old Masters, he became an advocate of more recent developments in French painting, to which he gave the name Post-Impressionism. He was the first figure to raise public awareness of modern art in Britain, and emphasised the formal properties of paintings over the 'associated ideas' conjured in the viewer by their representational content. He was described by the art historianKenneth Clark as 'incomparably the greatest influence on taste since Ruskin .. In so far as taste can be changed by one man, it was changed by Roger Fry'.[2] The taste Fry influenced was primarily that of the Anglophone world, and his successlay largely in alerting an educated public to a compelling version of recent artistic developments of the Parisian avant-garde.[3]

Life[edit]

Born in London, the son of the judge Edward Fry, he grew up in a wealthy Quaker family in Highgate. His siblings include Joan Mary Fry and Margery Fry, who became principal of Somerville College, Oxford. Fry was educated at Clifton College[4] and King's College, Cambridge,[5] where he was a member of the Conversazione Society, alongside freethinking men who would shape the foundation of his interest in the arts, including John McTaggart and Goldsworthy Lowes Dickinson. After taking a first in the Natural Science tripos, he went to Paris and then Italy to study art. Eventually he specialised in landscape painting.

In 1896, he married the artist Helen Coombe and they subsequently had two children, Pamela and Julian. Helen soon became seriously mentally ill, and in 1910 was committed to a mental institution, where she remained for the rest of her life. Fry took over the care of their children with the help of his sister, Joan Fry. That same year, Fry met the artists Vanessa Bell and her husband Clive Bell, and it was through them that he was introduced to the Bloomsbury Group. Vanessa's sister, the author Virginia Woolf later wrote in her biography of Fry that 'He had more knowledge and experience than the rest of us put together'.

In 1911, Fry began an affair with Vanessa Bell, who was recovering from a miscarriage. Fry offered her the tenderness and care she felt was lacking from her husband. They remained lifelong close friends, even though Fry's heart was broken in 1913 when Vanessa fell in love with Duncan Grant and decided to live permanently with him.

After short affairs with artists Nina Hamnett and Josette Coatmellec, Fry too found happiness with Helen Maitland Anrep. She became his emotional anchor for the rest of his life, although they never married (she too had had an unhappy first marriage, to the mosaicist Boris Anrep).

Fry died unexpectedly after a fall at his home in London. His death caused great sorrow among the members of the Bloomsbury Group, who loved him for his generosity and warmth. Vanessa Bell decorated his casket before his ashes were placed in the vault of Kings College Chapel in Cambridge. Virginia Woolf was entrusted with writing his biography,[6] published in 1940.

Artistic style[edit]

As a painter Fry was experimental (his work included a few abstracts), but his best pictures were straightforward naturalistic portraits,[7][8] although he did not pretend to be a professional portrait painter.[9] In his art he explored his own sensations and gradually his own personal visions and attitudes asserted themselves.[10] His work was considered to give pleasure, 'communicating the delight of unexpected beauty and which tempers the spectator's sense to a keener consciousness of its presence'.[11] Fry did not consider himself a great artist, 'only a serious artist with some sensibility and taste'.[12] He considered Cowdray Park his best painting: 'the best thing, in a way that I have done, the most complete at any rate'.[13]

Career[edit]

In the 1900s, Fry started to teach art history at the Slade School of Fine Art, University College London.

In 1903 Fry was involved in the foundation of The Burlington Magazine, the first scholarly periodical dedicated to art history in Britain. Fry was its co-editor between 1909 and 1919 (first with Lionel Cust, then with Cust and More Adey) but his influence on it continued until his death: Fry was on the consultative committee of The Burlington since its beginnings and when he left the editorship, following a dispute with Cust and Adey regarding the editorial policy on modern art, he was able to use his influence on the committee to choose the successor he considered appropriate, Robert Rattray Tatlock.[14] Fry wrote for The Burlington from 1903 until his death: he published over two hundred pieces on eclectic subjects – from children's drawings to bushman art. From the pages of The Burlington it is also possible to follow Fry's growing interest in Post-Impressionism.

On the technical side,there are articles on 'How to Build a Naive Bayes Classifier,' 'Python Development. Also, learn the origins of the tag from its creator, 'The Psychology of Tackling Hard Problems,' and more with the likes of Andrew Chen and Justin Kan. Our latest epic issue features Elon Musk as the cover story (courtesy of Stanford University's Entrepreneurship Corner), and 'How to Train Your Robot' by Nikos Michalakis, aka Dr. Hacking.

Fry's later reputation as a critic rested upon essays he wrote on Post-Impressionist painters.[15] and his most important theoretical statement is considered to be An essay in Aesthethics,[16] one of a selection of Fry' s writings on art extending over a period of twenty years published in 1920.[17] In 'An essay in Aesthethics', Fry argues that the response felt from examining art comes from the form of an artwork; meaning that it is the use of line, mass, colour and overall design that invokes an emotional response. His greatest gift was the ability to perceive the elements that give an artist his significance.[18]Fry was also a born letter writer, able to communicate his observations on art or human beings to his friends and family.[19]

In 1906 Fry was appointed Curator of Paintings at the Metropolitan Museum of Art in New York. This was also the year in which he 'discovered' the art of Paul Cézanne, the year the artist died, beginning the shift in his scholarly interests away from the Italian Old Masters and towards modern French art.

In November 1910, Fry organised the exhibition Manet and the Post-Impressionists (a term which he coined) at the Grafton Galleries, London. This exhibition was the first to prominently feature Gauguin, Manet, Matisse, and Van Gogh in England and brought their art to the public. Though the exhibition would eventually be widely celebrated, the sentiments at the time were much less favourable. This was due to the exhibition's selection of art that the public was unaccustomed to at the time. Fry was not immune to the backlash. Desmond MacCarthy, the secretary of the exhibition stated that 'by introducing the works of Cézanne, Matisse, Seurat, Van Gogh, Gauguin and Picasso to the British public, he smashed for a long time his reputation as an art critic. Kind people called him mad, and reminded others that his wife was in an asylum. The majority declared him to be a subverter of morals and art, and a blatant self-advertiser.' Yet the foreignness of 'post-impressionism' would inevitably disappear and eventually the exhibition would be regarded as a critical moment for art and culture.[20] Virginia Woolf later said, 'On or about December 1910 human character changed', referring to the effect this exhibit had on the world. Fry followed it up with the Second Post-Impressionist Exhibition in 1912. It was patronised by Lady Ottoline Morrell, with whom Fry had a fleeting romantic attachment.

English Heritage blue plaque for Fry and his Omega Studios at 33 Fitzroy Square, Fitzrovia, London Borough of Camden

In 1913 he founded the Omega Workshops, a design workshop based in London's Fitzroy Square, whose members included Vanessa Bell and Duncan Grant. In 1933, he was appointed the Slade Professor at Cambridge, a position that Fry had much desired.

Roger fry an essay in aesthetics

In September 1926 Fry wrote a definitive essay on Seurat in The Dial.[21] Fry also spent ten years translating, 'for his own pleasure',[22] the poems of the symbolist poet Stephane Mallarmé[23] Between 1929 and 1934, the BBC released a series of twelve broadcasts wherein Fry conveys his belief that art appreciation should begin with a sensibility to form as opposed to an inclination to praise art of high culture. Fry also argues that an African sculpture or a Chinese vase is just as deserving of study as a Greek sculpture.

A blue plaque was unveiled in Fitzroy Square on 20 May, 2010. His works can be seen in Tate Britain, the Ashmolean Museum, Leeds Art Gallery, National Portrait Gallery, Scottish National Gallery of Modern Art, Manchester Art Gallery and Somerville College.

Gallery[edit]

  • Goldsworthy Lowes Dickinson (1893)

  • Edward Carpenter (1894)

  • River with Poplars (ca. 1912)

  • Edith Sitwell, (1915)

    The Thoroughbred Breeders' Handbook. Highflyer International, 1997 - Thoroughbred horse - 107 pages. 0 Reviews What people are saying - Write a review. We haven't found any reviews in the usual places. We haven't found any reviews in the usual places. Bibliographic information. Title: The Thoroughbred Breeders' Handbook: Author: Clive. Thoroughbred Breeding: Pedigree Theories and the Science of Genetics is a book worth reading, though it could have been better. A friend recently gave me several boxes of books on breeding racehorses. Who wrote The Thoroughbred Breeders' Handbook. Harper analysed the pedigrees of a number of stakeswinners in New Zealand, and compared them. The thoroughbred breeders' handbook [Clive Harper] on Amazon.com. *FREE* shipping on qualifying offers. Thoroughbred breeders handbook harper.

  • Virginia Woolf, (1917)

  • Edith Sitwell, (1918)

  • Roger Fry, (1930–1934)

Books[edit]

  • Art and Commerce (1926)
  • Art History as an Academic Study (1933)
  • The Artist and Psycho-Analysis (1924)
  • Arts of Painting and Sculpture (1932)
  • Vision and Design (1920)
  • Transformations (1926)
  • Cézanne. A Study of His Development (1927)
  • Henri Matisse (1930)
  • Characteristics of French Art (1932)
  • Reflections on British Painting' (1934)
  • Giovanni Bellini (1899)
  • Duncan Grant (1923)
  • Flemish Art (1927)
  • Last Lectures (1933)
  • A Sampler of Castille (1923)
  • Twelve Original Woodcuts (1921)

Translations:

  • Some poems of Mallarme (1936)

Roger Fry Essay In Aesthetics

References[edit]

  1. ^'Search Results for England & Wales Births 1837-2006 - findmypast.co.uk'. search.findmypast.co.uk. Retrieved 9 April 2018.
  2. ^Chilvers. Ian , 'Fry, Roger.' Oxford Dictionary of Art and Artists. Oxford, 1990, ISBN9780199532940
  3. ^Reed, Christopher, Introduction,' A Roger Fry Reader' University of Chicago Press, Chicago 1996 ISBN978-0226266428
  4. ^'Clifton College Register' Muirhead, J.A.O. p95: Bristol; J.W Arrowsmith for Old Cliftonian Society; April, 1948
  5. ^'Fry, Roger (FRY885RE)'. A Cambridge Alumni Database. University of Cambridge.
  6. ^Wolf,Virginia, Roger Fry, A Biography, Harcourt Publishers, London, 1976 ISBN015678520X
  7. ^Chilvers, Ian, Dictionary of Art and Artists, Oxford University Press, 1990 ISBN9780199532940
  8. ^Portrait of Edward Carpenter, National Portrait Gallery, London
  9. ^Letter to Lady Fry,January 22, 1928
  10. ^Technical Appreciation by an artist ,Roger Fry, A Biography by Virginia Wolf, Harcourt,Brace and Co, New York ,1940
  11. ^Earp T. W. , critic of New Statesman – Retrospective Exhibition, Cooling Galleries, London, February 1931
  12. ^Letter to Marie Mauron June 20, 1920
  13. ^Letter to R. C. Trevelyan, November 20, 1903
  14. ^Sutton (ed.), Letters of Roger Fry (1972) pp. 448, 452
  15. ^Blunt, Anthony , Introduction Seurat, Phaidon Press, London, September 1965
  16. ^Bullen, J. B., Introduction Vision and Design by Roger Fry, Dover Paperbacks ,1998 ISBN9780486400877
  17. ^Fry, Roger Preface to Vision and design Chatto and Windus, London , 1920
  18. ^Sutton, Denys, Introduction Letters of Roger Fry Chatto and Windus, London, 1972 ISBN0701115998
  19. ^Sutton Denys, Preface to Letters of Roger Fry, Chatto and Windus, London 1972 ISBN0701115998
  20. ^ MacCarthy, Desmond, 'Desmond MacCarthy: The Post-Impressionist Exhibition of 1910', The Bloomsbury Group: A Collection of Memoirs and Commentary, University of Toronto Press, 1995; Print. Rev ed.
  21. ^Seurat, Phaidon Press, London , 1965
  22. ^Letter to Marie Mauron November 12, 1920
  23. ^Sutton, Denys, Biographical Notes, Letters of Roger Fry, Chatto and Windus, London 1972.

Sources[edit]

  • Virginia Woolf, Roger Fry: A Biography (1940) ISBN0-15-678520-X
  • Denys Sutton, Letters of Roger Fry (1972) ISBN0-7011-1599-8
  • Frances Spalding, Roger Fry: Art and Life, University of California Press, (1980) ISBN0-520-04126-7
  • David Boyd Haycock. 'A Crisis of Brilliance: Five Young British Artists and the Great War' (2009)
  • Christopher Reed, A Roger Fry Reader (1996) ISBN0-226-26642-7
  • Gal, Michalle. Aestheticism: Deep Formalism and the Emergence of Modernist Aesthetics. Peter Lang AG International Academic Publishers, 2015

Roger Fry An Essay In Aesthetics

External links[edit]

Wikiquote has quotations related to: Roger Fry
  • 112 paintings by or after Roger Fry at the Art UK site
Wikimedia Commons has media related to Roger Fry.
  • 'Post-Impressionism', Roger Fry's lecture on the closing of the 'Manet and the Post-Impressionists' exhibition at the Grafton Galleries, as published in The Fortnightly Review
  • 'Roger Fry, Walter Sickert and Post-Impressionism at the Grafton Galleries', a reflection by Prof. Marnin Young on the 1910-1911 exhibition


Roger

Roger Fry An Essay In Aesthetics

Retrieved from 'https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Roger_Fry&oldid=890210451'